BOOK
IV
1. THAT THE GENERAL WILL IS INDESTRUCTIBLE
As
long as several men in assembly regard themselves as
a single body, they have only a single will which is
concerned with their common preservation and general
well-being. In this case, all the springs of the State
are vigorous and simple and its rules clear and luminous;
there are no embroilments or conflicts of interests;
the common good is everywhere clearly apparent, and
only good sense is needed to perceive it. Peace, unity
and equality are the enemies of political subtleties.
Men who are upright and simple are difficult to deceive
because of their simplicity; lures and ingenious pretexts
fail to impose upon them, and they are not even subtle
enough to be dupes. When, among the happiest people
in the world, bands of peasants are seen regulating
affairs of State under an oak, and always acting wisely,
can we help scorning the ingenious methods of other
nations, which make themselves illustrious and wretched
with so much art and mystery?
A
State so governed needs very few laws; and, as it becomes
necessary to issue new ones, the necessity is universally
seen. The first man to propose them merely says what
all have already felt, and there is no question of factions
or intrigues or eloquence in order to secure the passage
into law of what every one has already decided to do,
as soon as he is sure that the rest will act with him.
Theorists
are led into error because, seeing only States that
have been from the beginning wrongly constituted, they
are struck by the impossibility of applying such a policy
to them. They make great game of all the absurdities
a clever rascal or an insinuating speaker might get
the people of Paris or London to believe. They do not
know that Cromwell would have been put to "the
bells" by the people of Berne, and the Duc de Beaufort
on the treadmill by the Genevese.
But
when the social bond begins to be relaxed and the State
to grow weak, when particular interests begin to make
themselves felt and the smaller societies to exercise
an influence over the larger, the common interest changes
and finds opponents: opinion is no longer unanimous;
the general will ceases to be the will of all; contradictory
views and debates arise; and the best advice is not
taken without question.
Finally,
when the State, on the eve of ruin, maintains only a
vain, illusory and formal existence, when in every heart
the social bond is broken, and the meanest interest
brazenly lays hold of the sacred name of "public
good," the general will becomes mute: all men,
guided by secret motives, no more give their views as
citizens than if the State had never been; and iniquitous
decrees directed solely to private interest get passed
under the name of laws.
Does
it follow from this that the general will is exterminated
or corrupted? Not at all: it is always constant, unalterable
and pure; but it is subordinated to other wills which
encroach upon its sphere. Each man, in detaching his
interest from the common interest, sees clearly that
he cannot entirely separate them; but his share in the
public mishaps seems to him negligible beside the exclusive
good he aims at making his own. Apart from this particular
good, he wills the general good in his own interest,
as strongly as any one else. Even in selling his vote
for money, he does not extinguish in himself the general
will, but only eludes it. The fault he commits is that
of changing the state of the question, and answering
something different from what he is asked. Instead of
saying, by his vote, "It is to the advantage of
the State," he says, "It is of advantage to
this or that man or party that this or that view should
prevail." Thus the law of public order in assemblies
is not so much to maintain in them the general will
as to secure that the question be always put to it,
and the answer always given by it.
I
could here set down many reflections on the simple right
of voting in every act of Sovereignty a right
which no one can take from the citizens and also
on the right of stating views, making proposals, dividing
and discussing, which the government is always most
careful to leave solely to its members, but this important
subject would need a treatise to itself, and it is impossible
to say everything in a single work.
It
may be seen, from the last chapter, that the way in
which general business is managed may give a clear enough
indication of the actual state of morals and the health
of the body politic. The more concert reigns in the
assemblies, that is, the nearer opinion approaches unanimity,
the greater is the dominance of the general will. On
the other hand, long debates, dissensions and tumult
proclaim the ascendancy of particular interests and
the decline of the State.
This
seems less clear when two or more orders enter into
the constitution, as patricians and plebeians did at
Rome; for quarrels between these two orders often disturbed
the comitia, even in the best days of the Republic.
But the exception is rather apparent than real; for
then, through the defect that is inherent in the body
politic, there were, so to speak, two States in one,
and what is not true of the two together is true of
either separately. Indeed, even in the most stormy times,
the plebiscita of the people, when the Senate did not
interfere with them, always went through quietly and
by large majorities. The citizens having but one interest,
the people had but a single will.
At
the other extremity of the circle, unanimity recurs;
this is the case when the citizens, having fallen into
servitude, have lost both liberty and will. Fear and
flattery then change votes into acclamation; deliberation
ceases, and only worship or malediction is left. Such
was the vile manner in which the senate expressed its
views under the Emperors. It did so sometimes with absurd
precautions. Tacitus observes that, under Otho, the
senators, while they heaped curses on Vitellius, contrived
at the same time to make a deafening noise, in order
that, should he ever become their master, he might not
know what each of them had said.
On
these various considerations depend the rules by which
the methods of counting votes and comparing opinions
should be regulated, according as the general will is
more or less easy to discover, and the State more or
less in its decline.
There
is but one law which, from its nature, needs unanimous
consent. This is the social compact; for civil association
is the most voluntary of all acts. Every man being born
free and his own master, no one, under any pretext whatsoever,
can make any man subject without his consent. To decide
that the son of a slave is born a slave is to decide
that he is not born a man.
If
then there are opponents when the social compact is
made, their opposition does not invalidate the contract,
but merely prevents them from being included in it.
They are foreigners among citizens. When the State is
instituted, residence constitutes consent; to dwell
within its territory is to submit to the Sovereign.34
Apart
from this primitive contract, the vote of the majority
always binds all the rest. This follows from the contract
itself. But it is asked how a man can be both free and
forced to conform to wills that are not his own. How
are the opponents at once free and subject to laws they
have not agreed to?
I
retort that the question is wrongly put. The citizen
gives his consent to all the laws, including those which
are passed in spite of his opposition, and even those
which punish him when he dares to break any of them.
The constant will of all the members of the State is
the general will; by virtue of it they are citizens
and free.35 When
in the popular assembly a law is proposed, what the
people is asked is not exactly whether it approves or
rejects the proposal, but whether it is in conformity
with the general will, which is their will. Each man,
in giving his vote, states his opinion on that point;
and the general will is found by counting votes. When
therefore the opinion that is contrary to my own prevails,
this proves neither more nor less than that I was mistaken,
and that what I thought to be the general will was not
so. If my particular opinion had carried the day I should
have achieved the opposite of what was my will; and
it is in that case that I should not have been free.
This
presupposes, indeed, that all the qualities of the general
will still reside in the majority: when they cease to
do so, whatever side a man may take, liberty is no longer
possible.
In
my earlier demonstration of how particular wills are
substituted for the general will in public deliberation,
I have adequately pointed out the practicable methods
of avoiding this abuse; and I shall have more to say
of them later on. I have also given the principles for
determining the proportional number of votes for declaring
that will. A difference of one vote destroys equality;
a single opponent destroys unanimity; but between equality
and unanimity, there are several grades of unequal division,
at each of which this proportion may be fixed in accordance
with the condition and the needs of the body politic.
There
are two general rules that may serve to regulate this
relation. First, the more grave and important the questions
discussed, the nearer should the opinion that is to
prevail approach unanimity. Secondly, the more the matter
in hand calls for speed, the smaller the prescribed
difference in the numbers of votes may be allowed to
become: where an instant decision has to be reached,
a majority of one vote should be enough. The first of
these two rules seems more in harmony with the laws,
and the second with practical affairs. In any case,
it is the combination of them that gives the best proportions
for determining the majority necessary.
In
the elections of the prince and the magistrates, which
are, as I have said, complex acts, there are two possible
methods of procedure, choice and lot. Both have been
employed in various republics, and a highly complicated
mixture of the two still survives in the election of
the Doge at Venice.
"Election
by lot," says Montesquieu, "is democratic
in nature."E3
I agree that it is so; but in what sense? "The
lot," he goes on, "is a way of making choice
that is unfair to nobody; it leaves each citizen a reasonable
hope of serving his country." These are not reasons.
If
we bear in mind that the election of rulers is a function
of government, and not of Sovereignty, we shall see
why the lot is the method more natural to democracy,
in which the administration is better in proportion
as the number of its acts is small.
In
every real democracy, magistracy is not an advantage,
but a burdensome charge which cannot justly be imposed
on one individual rather than another. The law alone
can lay the charge on him on whom the lot falls. For,
the conditions being then the same for all, and the
choice not depending on any human will, there is no
particular application to alter the universality of
the law.
In
an aristocracy, the prince chooses the prince, the government
is preserved by itself, and voting is rightly ordered.
The
instance of the election of the Doge of Venice confirms,
instead of destroying, this distinction; the mixed form
suits a mixed government. For it is an error to take
the government of Venice for a real aristocracy. If
the people has no share in the government, the nobility
is itself the people. A host of poor Barnabotes never
gets near any magistracy, and its nobility consists
merely in the empty title of Excellency, and in the
right to sit in the Great Council. As this Great Council
is as numerous as our General Council at Geneva, its
illustrious members have no more privileges than our
plain citizens. It is indisputable that, apart from
the extreme disparity between the two republics, the
bourgeoisie of Geneva is exactly equivalent to
the patriciate of Venice; our natives
and inhabitants correspond to the townsmen
and the people of Venice; our peasants
correspond to the subjects on the mainland; and,
however that republic be regarded, if its size be left
out of account, its government is no more aristocratic
than our own. The whole difference is that, having no
life-ruler, we do not, like Venice, need to use the
lot.
Election
by lot would have few disadvantages in a real democracy,
in which, as equality would everywhere exist in morals
and talents as well as in principles and fortunes, it
would become almost a matter of indifference who was
chosen. But I have already said that a real democracy
is only an ideal.
When
choice and lot are combined, positions that require
special talents, such as military posts, should be filled
by the former; the latter does for cases, such as judicial
offices, in which good sense, justice, and integrity
are enough, because in a State that is well constituted,
these qualities are common to all the citizens.
Neither
lot nor vote has any place in monarchical government.
The monarch being by right sole prince and only magistrate,
the choice of his lieutenants belongs to none but him.
When the Abbé de Saint-Pierre proposed that the
Councils of the King of France should be multiplied,
and their members elected by ballot, he did not see
that he was proposing to change the form of government.
I
should now speak of the methods of giving and counting
opinions in the assembly of the people; but perhaps
an account of this aspect of the Roman constitution
will more forcibly illustrate all the rules I could
lay down. It is worth the while of a judicious reader
to follow in some detail the working of public and private
affairs in a Council consisting of two hundred thousand
men.
We
are without well-certified records of the first period
of Rome's existence; it even appears very probable that
most of the stories told about it are fables; indeed,
generally speaking, the most instructive part of the
history of peoples, that which deals with their foundation,
is what we have least of. Experience teaches us every
day what causes lead to the revolutions of empires;
but, as no new peoples are now formed, we have almost
nothing beyond conjecture to go upon in explaining how
they were created.
The
customs we find established show at least that these
customs had an origin. The traditions that go back to
those origins, that have the greatest authorities behind
them, and that are confirmed by the strongest proofs,
should pass for the most certain. These are the rules
I have tried to follow in inquiring how the freest and
most powerful people on earth exercised its supreme
power.
After
the foundation of Rome, the new-born republic, that
is, the army of its founder, composed of Albans, Sabines
and foreigners, was divided into three classes, which,
from this division, took the name of tribes.
Each of these tribes was subdivided into ten curiæ,
and each curia into decuriæ, headed
by leaders called curiones and decuriones.
Besides
this, out of each tribe was taken a body of one hundred
Equites or Knights, called a century,
which shows that these divisions, being unnecessary
in a town, were at first merely military. But an instinct
for greatness seems to have led the little township
of Rome to provide itself in advance with a political
system suitable for the capital of the world.
Out
of this original division an awkward situation soon
arose. The tribes of the Albans (Ramnenses) and the
Sabines (Tatienses) remained always in the same condition,
while that of the foreigners (Luceres) continually grew
as more and more foreigners came to live at Rome, so
that it soon surpassed the others in strength. Servius
remedied this dangerous fault by changing the principle
of cleavage, and substituting for the racial division,
which he abolished, a new one based on the quarter of
the town inhabited by each tribe. Instead of three tribes
he created four, each occupying and named after one
of the hills of Rome. Thus, while redressing the inequality
of the moment, he also provided for the future; and
in order that the division might be one of persons as
well as localities, he forbade the inhabitants of one
quarter to migrate to another, and so prevented the
mingling of the races.
He
also doubled the three old centuries of Knights and
added twelve more, still keeping the old names, and
by this simple and prudent method, succeeded in making
a distinction between the body of Knights, and the people,
without a murmur from the latter.
To
the four urban tribes Servius added fifteen others called
rural tribes, because they consisted of those who lived
in the country, divided into fifteen cantons. Subsequently,
fifteen more were created, and the Roman people finally
found itself divided into thirty-five tribes, as it
remained down to the end of the Republic.
The
distinction between urban and rural tribes had one effect
which is worth mention, both because it is without parallel
elsewhere, and because to it Rome owed the preservation
of her morality and the enlargement of her empire. We
should have expected that the urban tribes would soon
monopolise power and honours, and lose no time in bringing
the rural tribes into disrepute; but what happened was
exactly the reverse. The taste of the early Romans for
country life is well known. This taste they owed to
their wise founder, who made rural and military labours
go along with liberty, and, so to speak, relegated to
the town arts, crafts, intrigue, fortune and slavery.
Since
therefore all Rome's most illustrious citizens lived
in the fields and tilled the earth, men grew used to
seeking there alone the mainstays of the republic. This
condition, being that of the best patricians, was honoured
by all men; the simple and laborious life of the villager
was preferred to the slothful and idle life of the bourgeoisie
of Rome; and he who, in the town, would have been but
a wretched proletarian, became, as a labourer in the
fields, a respected citizen. Not without reason, says
Varro, did our great-souled ancestors establish in the
village the nursery of the sturdy and valiant men who
defended them in time of war and provided for their
sustenance in time of peace. Pliny states positively
that the country tribes were honoured because of the
men of whom they were composed; while cowards men wished
to dishonour were transferred, as a public disgrace,
to the town tribes. The Sabine Appius Claudius, when
he had come to settle in Rome, was loaded with honours
and enrolled in a rural tribe, which subsequently took
his family name. Lastly, freedmen always entered the
urban, arid never the rural, tribes: nor is there a
single example, throughout the Republic, of a freedman,
though he had become a citizen, reaching any magistracy.
This
was an excellent rule; but it was carried so far that
in the end it led to a change and certainly to an abuse
in the political system.
First
the censors, after having for a long time claimed the
right of transferring citizens arbitrarily from one
tribe to another, allowed most persons to enrol themselves
in whatever tribe they pleased. This permission certainly
did no good, and further robbed the censorship of one
of its greatest resources. Moreover, as the great and
powerful all got themselves enrolled in the country
tribes, while the freedmen who had become citizens remained
with the populace in the town tribes, both soon ceased
to have any local or territorial meaning, and all were
so confused that the members of one could not be told
from those of another except by the registers; so that
the idea of the word tribe became personal instead
of real, or rather came to be little more than a chimera.
It
happened in addition that the town tribes, being more
on the spot, were often the stronger in the comitia
and sold the State to those who stooped to buy the votes
of the rabble composing them.
As
the founder had set up ten curiæ in each
tribe, the whole Roman people, which was then contained
within the walls, consisted of thirty curiæ,
each with its temples, its gods, its officers, its priests
and its festivals, which were called compitalia
and corresponded to the paganalia, held in later
times by the rural tribes.
When
Servius made his new division, as the thirty curiæ
could not be shared equally between his four tribes,
and as he was unwilling to interfere with them, they
became a further division of the inhabitants of Rome,
quite independent of the tribes: but in the case of
the rural tribes and their members there was no question
of curiæ, as the tribes had then become
a purely civil institution, and, a new system of levying
troops having been introduced, the military divisions
of Romulus were superfluous. Thus, although every citizen
was enrolled in a tribe, there were very many who were
not members of a curia.
Servius
made yet a third division, quite distinct from the two
we have mentioned, which became, in its effects, the
most important of all. He distributed the whole Roman
people into six classes, distinguished neither by place
nor by person, but by wealth; the first classes included
the rich, the last the poor, and those between persons
of moderate means. These six classes were subdivided
into one hundred and ninety-three other bodies, called
centuries, which were so divided that the first class
alone comprised more than half of them, while the last
comprised only one. Thus the class that had the smallest
number of members had the largest number of centuries,
and the whole of the last class only counted as a single
subdivision, although it alone included more than half
the inhabitants of Rome.
In
order that the people might have the less insight into
the results of this arrangement, Servius tried to give
it a military tone: in the second class he inserted
two centuries of armourers, and in the fourth two of
makers of instruments of war: in each class, except
the last, he distinguished young and old, that is, those
who were under an obligation to bear arms and those
whose age gave them legal exemption. It was this distinction,
rather than that of wealth, which required frequent
repetition of the census or counting. Lastly, he ordered
that the assembly should be held in the Campus Martius,
and that all who were of age to serve should come there
armed.
The
reason for his not making in the last class also the
division of young and old was that the populace, of
whom it was composed, was not given the right to bear
arms for its country: a man had to possess a hearth
to acquire the right to defend it, and of all the troops
of beggars who to-day lend lustre to the armies of kings,
there is perhaps not one who would not have been driven
with scorn out of a Roman cohort, at a time when soldiers
were the defenders of liberty.
In
this last class, however, proletarians were distinguished
from capite censi. The former, not quite reduced
to nothing, at least gave the State citizens, and sometimes,
when the need was pressing, even soldiers. Those who
had nothing at all, and could be numbered only by counting
heads, were regarded as of absolutely no account, and
Marius was the first who stooped to enrol them.
Without
deciding now whether this third arrangement was good
or bad in itself, I think I may assert that it could
have been made practicable only by the simple morals,
the disinterestedness, the liking for agriculture and
the scorn for commerce and for love of gain which characterised
the early Romans. Where is the modern people among whom
consuming greed, unrest, intrigue, continual removals,
and perpetual changes of fortune, could let such a system
last for twenty years without turning the State upside
down? We must indeed observe that morality and the censorship,
being stronger than this institution, corrected its
defects at Rome, and that the rich man found himself
degraded to the class of the poor for making too much
display of his riches.
From
all this it is easy to understand why only five classes
are almost always mentioned, though there were really
six. The sixth, as it furnished neither soldiers to
the army nor votes in the Campus Martius,36
and was almost without function in the State, was seldom
regarded as of any account.
These
were the various ways in which the Roman people was
divided. Let us now see the effect on the assemblies.
When lawfully summoned, these were called comitia:
they were usually held in the public square at Rome
or in the Campus Martius, and were distinguished as
comitia curiata, comitia centuriata, and comitia
tributa, according to the form under which they
were convoked. The comitia curiata were founded
by Romulus; the centuriata by Servius; and the
tributa by the tribunes of the people. No law
received its sanction and no magistrate was elected,
save in the comitia; and as every citizen was enrolled
in a curia, a century, or a tribe, it follows
that no citizen was excluded from the right of voting,
and that the Roman people was truly sovereign both de
jure and de facto.
For
the comitia to be lawfully assembled, and for their
acts to have the force of law, three conditions were
necessary. First, the body or magistrate convoking them
had to possess the necessary authority; secondly, the
assembly had to be held on a day allowed by law; and
thirdly, the auguries had to be favourable.
The
reason for the first regulation needs no explanation;
the second is a matter of policy. Thus, the comitia
might not be held on festivals or market-days, when
the country-folk, coming to Rome on business, had not
time to spend the day in the public square. By means
of the third, the senate held in check the proud and
restive people, and meetly restrained the ardour of
seditious tribunes, who, however, found more than one
way of escaping this hindrance.
Laws
and the election of rulers were not the only questions
submitted to the judgment of the comitia: as the Roman
people had taken on itself the most important functions
of government, it may be said that the lot of Europe
was regulated in its assemblies. The variety of their
objects gave rise to the various forms these took, according
to the matters on which they had to pronounce.
In
order to judge of these various forms, it is enough
to compare them. Romulus, when he set up curia,
had in view the checking of the senate by the people,
and of the people by the senate, while maintaining his
ascendancy over both alike. He therefore gave the people,
by means of this assembly, all the authority of numbers
to balance that of power and riches, which he left to
the patricians. But, after the spirit of monarchy, he
left all the same a greater advantage to the patricians
in the influence of their clients on the majority of
votes. This excellent institution of patron and client
was a masterpiece of statesmanship and humanity without
which the patriciate, being flagrantly in contradiction
to the republican spirit, could not have survived. Rome
alone has the honour of having given to the world this
great example, which never led to any abuse, and yet
has never been followed.
As
the assemblies by curiæ persisted under
the kings till the time of Servius, and the reign of
the later Tarquin was not regarded as legitimate, royal
laws were called generally leges curiatæ.
Under
the Republic, the curiæ, still confined
to the four urban tribes, and including only the populace
of Rome, suited neither the senate, which led the patricians,
nor the tribunes, who, though plebeians, were at the
head of the well-to-do citizens. They therefore fell
into disrepute, and their degradation was such, that
thirty lictors used to assemble and do what the comitia
curiata should have done.
The
division by centuries was so favourable to the aristocracy
that it is hard to see at first how the senate ever
failed to carry the day in the comitia bearing their
name, by which the consuls, the censors and the other
curule magistrates were elected. Indeed, of the hundred
and ninety-three centuries into which the six classes
of the whole Roman people were divided, the first class
contained ninety-eight; and, as voting went solely by
centuries, this class alone had a majority over all
the rest. When all these centuries were in agreement,
the rest of the votes were not even taken; the decision
of the smallest number passed for that of the multitude,
and it may be said that, in the comitia centuriata,
decisions were regulated far more by depth of purses
than by the number of votes.
But
this extreme authority was modified in two ways. First,
the tribunes as a rule, and always a great number of
plebeians, belonged to the class of the rich, and so
counterbalanced the influence of the patricians in the
first class.
The
second way was this. Instead of causing the centuries
to vote throughout in order, which would have meant
beginning always with the first, the Romans always chose
one by lot which proceeded alone to the election; after
this all the centuries were summoned another day according
to their rank, and the same election was repeated, and
as a rule confirmed. Thus the authority of example was
taken away from rank, and given to the lot on a democratic
principle.
From
this custom resulted a further advantage. The citizens
from the country had time, between the two elections,
to inform themselves of the merits of the candidate
who had been provisionally nominated, and did not have
to vote without knowledge of the case. But, under the
pretext of hastening matters, the abolition of this
custom was achieved, and both elections were held on
the same day.
The
comitia tributa were properly the council of
the Roman people. They were convoked by the tribunes
alone; at them the tribunes were elected and passed
their plebiscita. The senate not only had no standing
in them, but even no right to be present; and the senators,
being forced to obey laws on which they could not vote,
were in this respect less free than the meanest citizens.
This injustice was altogether ill-conceived, and was
alone enough to invalidate the decrees of a body to
which all its members were not admitted. Had all the
patricians attended the comitia by virtue of the right
they had as citizens, they would not, as mere private
individuals, have had any considerable influence on
a vote reckoned by counting heads, where the meanest
proletarian was as good as the princeps senatus.
It
may be seen, therefore, that besides the order which
was achieved by these various ways of distributing so
great a people and taking its votes, the various methods
were not reducible to forms indifferent in themselves,
but the results of each were relative to the objects
which caused it to be preferred.
Without
going here into further details, we may gather from
what has been said above that the comitia tributa
were the most favourable to popular government, and
the comitia centuriata to aristocracy. The comitia
curiata, in which the populace of Rome formed the
majority, being fitted only to further tyranny and evil
designs, naturally fell into disrepute, and even seditious
persons abstained from using a method which too clearly
revealed their projects. It is indisputable that the
whole majesty of the Roman people lay solely in the
comitia centuriata, which alone included all;
for the comitia curiata excluded the rural tribes,
and the comitia tributa the senate and the patricians.
As
for the method of taking the vote, it was among the
ancient Romans as simple as their morals, although not
so simple as at Sparta. Each man declared his vote aloud,
and a clerk duly wrote it down; the majority in each
tribe determined the vote of the tribe, the majority
of the tribes that of the people, and so with curiæ
and centuries. This custom was good as long as honesty
was triumphant among the citizens, and each man was
ashamed to vote publicly in favour of an unjust proposal
or an unworthy subject; but, when the people grew corrupt
and votes were bought, it was fitting that voting should
be secret in order that purchasers might be restrained
by mistrust, and rogues be given the means of not being
traitors.
I
know that Cicero attacks this change, and attributes
partly to it the ruin of the Republic. But though I
feel the weight Cicero's authority must carry on such
a point, I cannot agree with him; I hold, on the contrary,
that, for want of enough such changes, the destruction
of the State must be hastened. Just as the regimen of
health does not suit the sick, we should not wish to
govern a people that has been corrupted by the laws
that a good people requires. There is no better proof
of this rule than the long life of the Republic of Venice,
of which the shadow still exists, solely because its
laws are suitable only for men who are wicked.
The
citizens were provided, therefore, with tablets by means
of which each man could vote without any one knowing
how he voted: new methods were also introduced for collecting
the tablets, for counting voices, for comparing numbers,
etc.; but all these precautions did not prevent the
good faith of the officers charged with these functions37
from being often suspect. Finally, to prevent intrigues
and trafficking in votes, edicts were issued; but their
very number proves how useless they were.
Towards
the close of the Republic, it was often necessary to
have recourse to extraordinary expedients in order to
supplement the inadequacy of the laws. Sometimes miracles
were supposed; but this method, while it might impose
on the people, could not impose on those who governed.
Sometimes an assembly was hastily called together, before
the candidates had time to form their factions: sometimes
a whole sitting was occupied with talk, when it was
seen that the people had been won over and was on the
point of taking up a wrong position. But in the end
ambition eluded all attempts to check it; and the most
incredible fact of all is that, in the midst of all
these abuses, the vast people, thanks to its ancient
regulations, never ceased to elect magistrates, to pass
laws, to judge cases, and to carry through business
both public and private, almost as easily as the senate
itself could have done.
When
an exact proportion cannot be established between the
constituent parts of the State, or when causes that
cannot be removed continually alter the relation of
one part to another, recourse is had to the institution
of a peculiar magistracy that enters into no corporate
unity with the rest. This restores to each term its
right relation to the others, and provides a link or
middle term between either prince and people, or prince
and Sovereign, or, if necessary, both at once.
This
body, which I shall call the tribunate, is the
preserver of the laws and of the legislative power.
It serves sometimes to protect the Sovereign against
the government, as the tribunes of the people did at
Rome; sometimes to uphold the government against the
people, as the Council of Ten now does at Venice; and
sometimes to maintain the balance between the two, as
the Ephors did at Sparta.
The
tribunate is not a constituent part of the city, and
should have no share in either legislative or executive
power; but this very fact makes its own power the greater:
for, while it can do nothing, it can prevent anything
from being done. It is more sacred and more revered,
as the defender of the laws, than the prince who executes
them, or than the Sovereign which ordains them. This
was seen very clearly at Rome, when the proud patricians,
for all their scorn of the people, were forced to bow
before one of its officers, who had neither auspices
nor jurisdiction.
The
tribunate, wisely tempered, is the strongest support
a good constitution can have; but if its strength is
ever so little excessive, it upsets the whole State.
Weakness, on the other hand, is not natural to it: provided
it is something, it is never less than it should be.
It
degenerates into tyranny when it usurps the executive
power, which it should confine itself to restraining,
and when it tries to dispense with the laws, which it
should confine itself to protecting. The immense power
of the Ephors, harmless as long as Sparta preserved
its morality, hastened corruption when once it had begun.
The blood of Agis, slaughtered by these tyrants, was
avenged by his successor; the crime and the punishment
of the Ephors alike hastened the destruction of the
republic, and after Cleomenes Sparta ceased to be of
any account. Rome perished in the same way: the excessive
power of the tribunes, which they had usurped by degrees,
finally served, with the help of laws made to secure
liberty, as a safeguard for the emperors who destroyed
it. As for the Venetian Council of Ten, it is a tribunal
of blood, an object of horror to patricians and people
alike; and, so far from giving a lofty protection to
the laws, it does nothing, now they have become degraded,
but strike in the darkness blows of which no one dare
take note.
The
tribunate, like the government, grows weak as the number
of its members increases. When the tribunes of the Roman
people, who first numbered only two, and then five,
wished to double that number, the senate let them do
so, in the confidence that it could use one to check
another, as indeed it afterwards freely did.
The
best method of preventing usurpations by so formidable
a body, though no government has yet made use of it,
would be not to make it permanent, but to regulate the
periods during which it should remain in abeyance. These
intervals, which should not be long enough to give abuses
time to grow strong, may be so fixed by law that they
can easily be shortened at need by extraordinary commissions.
This
method seems to me to have no disadvantages, because,
as I have said, the tribunate, which forms no part of
the constitution, can be removed without the constitution
being affected. It seems to be also efficacious, because
a newly restored magistrate starts not with the power
his predecessor exercised, but with that which the law
allows him.
The
inflexibility of the laws, which prevents them from
adapting themselves to circumstances, may, in certain
cases, render them disastrous, and make them bring about,
at a time of crisis, the ruin of the State. The order
and slowness of the forms they enjoin require a space
of time which circumstances sometimes withhold. A thousand
cases against which the legislator has made no provision
may present themselves, and it is a highly necessary
part of foresight to be conscious that everything cannot
be foreseen.
It
is wrong therefore to wish to make political institutions
so strong as to render it impossible to suspend their
operation. Even Sparta allowed its laws to lapse.
However,
none but the greatest dangers can counterbalance that
of changing the public order, and the sacred power of
the laws should never be arrested save when the existence
of the country is at stake. In these rare and obvious
cases, provision is made for the public security by
a particular act entrusting it to him who is most worthy.
This commitment may be carried out in either of two
ways, according to the nature of the danger.
If
increasing the activity of the government is a sufficient
remedy, power is concentrated in the hands of one or
two of its members: in this case the change is not in
the authority of the laws, but only in the form of administering
them. If, on the other hand, the peril is of such a
kind that the paraphernalia of the laws are an obstacle
to their preservation, the method is to nominate a supreme
ruler, who shall silence all the laws and suspend for
a moment the sovereign authority. In such a case, there
is no doubt about the general will, and it is clear
that the people's first intention is that the State
shall not perish. Thus the suspension of the legislative
authority is in no sense its abolition; the magistrate
who silences it cannot make it speak; he dominates it,
but cannot represent it. He can do anything, except
make laws.
The
first method was used by the Roman senate when, in a
consecrated formula, it charged the consuls to provide
for the safety of the Republic. The second was employed
when one of the two consuls nominated a dictator:38
a custom Rome borrowed from Alba.
During
the first period of the Republic, recourse was very
often had to the dictatorship, because the State had
not yet a firm enough basis to be able to maintain itself
by the strength of its constitution alone. As the state
of morality then made superfluous many of the precautions
which would have been necessary at other times, there
was no fear that a dictator would abuse his authority,
or try to keep it beyond his term of office. On the
contrary, so much power appeared to be burdensome to
him who was clothed with it, and he made all speed to
lay it down, as if taking the place of the laws had
been too troublesome and too perilous a position to
retain.
It
is therefore the danger not of its abuse, but of its
cheapening, that makes me attack the indiscreet use
of this supreme magistracy in the earliest times. For
as long as it was freely employed at elections, dedications
and purely formal functions, there was danger of its
becoming less formidable in time of need, and of men
growing accustomed to regarding as empty a title that
was used only on occasions of empty ceremonial.
Towards
the end of the Republic, the Romans, having grown more
circumspect, were as unreasonably sparing in the use
of the dictatorship as they had formerly been lavish.
It is easy to see that their fears were without foundation,
that the weakness of the capital secured it against
the magistrates who were in its midst; that a dictator
might, in certain cases, defend the public liberty,
but could never endanger it; and that the chains of
Rome would be forged, not in Rome itself, but in her
armies. The weak resistance offered by Marius to Sulla,
and by Pompey to Cæsar, clearly showed what was
to be expected from authority at home against force
from abroad.
This
misconception led the Romans to make great mistakes;
such, for example, as the failure to nominate a dictator
in the Catilinarian conspiracy. For, as only the city
itself, with at most some province in Italy, was concerned,
the unlimited authority the laws gave to the dictator
would have enabled him to make short work of the conspiracy,
which was, in fact, stifled only by a combination of
lucky chances human prudence had no right to expect.
Instead,
the senate contented itself with entrusting its whole
power to the consuls, so that Cicero, in order to take
effective action, was compelled on a capital point to
exceed his powers; and if, in the first transports of
joy, his conduct was approved, he was justly called,
later on, to account for the blood of citizens spilt
in violation of the laws. Such a reproach could never
have been levelled at a dictator. But the consul's eloquence
carried the day; and he himself, Roman though he was,
loved his own glory better than his country, and sought,
not so much the most lawful and secure means of saving
the State, as to get for himself the whole honour of
having done so.39
He was therefore justly honoured as the liberator of
Rome, and also justly punished as a law-breaker. However
brilliant his recall may have been, it was undoubtedly
an act of pardon.
However
this important trust be conferred, it is important that
its duration should be fixed at a very brief period,
incapable of being ever prolonged. In the crises which
lead to its adoption, the State is either soon lost,
or soon saved; and, the present need passed, the dictatorship
becomes either tyrannical or idle. At Rome, where dictators
held office for six months only, most of them abdicated
before their time was up. If their term had been longer,
they might well have tried to prolong it still further,
as the decemvirs did when chosen for a year. The dictator
had only time to provide against the need that had caused
him to be chosen; he had none to think of further projects.
As
the law is the declaration of the general will, the
censorship is the declaration of the public judgment:
public opinion is the form of law which the censor administers,
and, like the prince, only applies to particular cases.
The
censorial tribunal, so far from being the arbiter of
the people's opinion, only declares it, and, as soon
as the two part company, its decisions are null and
void.
It
is useless to distinguish the morality of a nation from
the objects of its esteem; both depend on the same principle
and are necessarily indistinguishable. There is no people
on earth the choice of whose pleasures is not decided
by opinion rather than nature. Right men's opinions,
and their morality will purge itself. Men always love
what is good or what they find good; it is in judging
what is good that they go wrong. This judgment, therefore,
is what must be regulated. He who judges of morality
judges of honour; and he who judges of honour finds
his law in opinion.
The
opinions of a people are derived from its constitution;
although the law does not regulate morality, it is legislation
that gives it birth. When legislation grows weak, morality
degenerates; but in such cases the judgment of the censors
will not do what the force of the laws has failed to
effect.
From
this it follows that the censorship may be useful for
the preservation of morality, but can never be so for
its restoration. Set up censors while the laws are vigorous;
as soon as they have lost their vigour, all hope is
gone; no legitimate power can retain force when the
laws have lost it.
The
censorship upholds morality by preventing opinion from
growing corrupt, by preserving its rectitude by means
of wise applications, and sometimes even by fixing it
when it is still uncertain. The employment of seconds
in duels, which had been carried to wild extremes in
the kingdom of France, was done away with merely by
these words in a royal edict: "As for those who
are cowards enough to call upon seconds." This
judgment, in anticipating that of the public, suddenly
decided it. But when edicts from the same source tried
to pronounce duelling itself an act of cowardice, as
indeed it is, then, since common opinion does not regard
it as such, the public took no notice of a decision
on a point on which its mind was already made up.
I
have stated elsewhere40
that as public opinion is not subject to any constraint,
there need be no trace of it in the tribunal set up
to represent it. It is impossible to admire too much
the art with which this resource, which we moderns have
wholly lost, was employed by the Romans, and still more
by the Lacedæmonians.
A
man of bad morals having made a good proposal in the
Spartan Council, the Ephors neglected it, and caused
the same proposal to be made by a virtuous citizen.
What an honour for the one, and what a disgrace for
the other, without praise or blame of either! Certain
drunkards from Samos41
polluted the tribunal of the Ephors: the next day, a
public edict gave Samians permission to be filthy. An
actual punishment would not have been so severe as such
an impunity. When Sparta has pronounced on what is or
is not right, Greece makes no appeal from her judgments.
At
first men had no kings save the gods, and no government
save theocracy. They reasoned like Caligula, and, at
that period, reasoned aright. It takes a long time for
feeling so to change that men can make up their minds
to take their equals as masters, in the hope that they
will profit by doing so.
From
the mere fact that God was set over every political
society, it followed that there were as many gods as
peoples. Two peoples that were strangers the one to
the other, and almost always enemies, could not long
recognise the same master: two armies giving battle
could not obey the same leader. National divisions thus
led to polytheism, and this in turn gave rise to theological
and civil intolerance, which, as we shall see hereafter,
are by nature the same.
The
fancy the Greeks had for rediscovering their gods among
the barbarians arose from the way they had of regarding
themselves as the natural Sovereigns of such peoples.
But there is nothing so absurd as the erudition which
in our days identifies and confuses gods of different
nations. As if Moloch, Saturn, and Chronos could be
the same god! As if the Phoenician Baal, the Greek Zeus,
and the Latin Jupiter could be the same! As if there
could still be anything common to imaginary beings with
different names!
If
it is asked how in pagan times, where each State had
its cult and its gods, there were no wars of religion,
I answer that it was precisely because each State, having
its own cult as well as its own government, made no
distinction between its gods and its laws. Political
war was also theological; the provinces of the gods
were, so to speak, fixed by the boundaries of nations.
The god of one people had no right over another. The
gods of the pagans were not jealous gods; they shared
among themselves the empire of the world: even Moses
and the Hebrews sometimes lent themselves to this view
by speaking of the God of Israel. It is true, they regarded
as powerless the gods of the Canaanites, a proscribed
people condemned to destruction, whose place they were
to take; but remember how they spoke of the divisions
of the neighbouring peoples they were forbidden to attack!
"Is not the possession of what belongs to your
god Chamos lawfully your due?" said Jephthah to
the Ammonites. "We have the same title to the lands
our conquering God has made his own."42
Here, I think, there is a recognition that the rights
of Chamos and those of the God of Israel are of the
same nature.
But
when the Jews, being subject to the Kings of Babylon,
and, subsequently, to those of Syria, still obstinately
refused to recognise any god save their own, their refusal
was regarded as rebellion against their conqueror, and
drew down on them the persecutions we read of in their
history, which are without parallel till the coming
of Christianity.43
Every
religion, therefore, being attached solely to the laws
of the State which prescribed it, there was no way of
converting a people except by enslaving it, and there
could be no missionaries save conquerors. The obligation
to change cults being the law to which the vanquished
yielded, it was necessary to be victorious before suggesting
such a change. So far from men fighting for the gods,
the gods, as in Homer, fought for men; each asked his
god for victory, and repayed him with new altars. The
Romans, before taking a city, summoned its gods to quit
it; and, in leaving the Tarentines their outraged gods,
they regarded them as subject to their own and compelled
to do them homage. They left the vanquished their gods
as they left them their laws. A wreath to the Jupiter
of the Capitol was often the only tribute they imposed.
Finally,
when, along with their empire, the Romans had spread
their cult and their gods, and had themselves often
adopted those of the vanquished, by granting to both
alike the rights of the city, the peoples of that vast
empire insensibly found themselves with multitudes of
gods and cults, everywhere almost the same; and thus
paganism throughout the known world finally came to
be one and the same religion.
It
was in these circumstances that Jesus came to set up
on earth a spiritual kingdom, which, by separating the
theological from the political system, made the State
no longer one, and brought about the internal divisions
which have never ceased to trouble Christian peoples.
As the new idea of a kingdom of the other world could
never have occurred to pagans, they always looked on
the Christians as really rebels, who, while feigning
to submit, were only waiting for the chance to make
themselves independent and their masters, and to usurp
by guile the authority they pretended in their weakness
to respect. This was the cause of the persecutions.
What
the pagans had feared took place. Then everything changed
its aspect: the humble Christians changed their language,
and soon this so-called kingdom of the other world turned,
under a visible leader, into the most violent of earthly
despotisms.
However,
as there have always been a prince and civil laws, this
double power and conflict of jurisdiction have made
all good polity impossible in Christian States; and
men have never succeeded in finding out whether they
were bound to obey the master or the priest.
Several
peoples, however, even in Europe and its neighbourhood,
have desired without success to preserve or restore
the old system: but the spirit of Christianity has everywhere
prevailed. The sacred cult has always remained or again
become independent of the Sovereign, and there has been
no necessary link between it and the body of the State.
Mahomet held very sane views, and linked his political
system well together; and, as long as the form of his
government continued under the caliphs who succeeded
him, that government was indeed one, and so far good.
But the Arabs, having grown prosperous, lettered, civilised,
slack and cowardly, were conquered by barbarians: the
division between the two powers began again; and, although
it is less apparent among the Mahometans than among
the Christians, it none the less exists, especially
in the sect of Ali, and there are States, such as Persia,
where it is continually making itself felt.
Among
us, the Kings of England have made themselves heads
of the Church, and the Czars have done the same: but
this title has made them less its masters than its ministers;
they have gained not so much the right to change it,
as the power to maintain it: they are not its legislators,
but only its princes. Wherever the clergy is a corporate
body,44 it is master
and legislator in its own country. There are thus two
powers, two Sovereigns, in England and in Russia, as
well as elsewhere.
Of
all Christian writers, the philosopher Hobbes alone
has seen the evil and how to remedy it, and has dared
to propose the reunion of the two heads of the eagle,
and the restoration throughout of political unity, without
which no State or government will ever be rightly constituted.
But he should have seen that the masterful spirit of
Christianity is incompatible with his system, and that
the priestly interest would always be stronger than
that of the State. It is not so much what is false and
terrible in his political theory, as what is just and
true, that has drawn down hatred on it.45
I
believe that if the study of history were developed
from this point of view, it would be easy to refute
the contrary opinions of Bayle and Warburton, one of
whom holds that religion can be of no use to the body
politic, while the other, on the contrary, maintains
that Christianity is its strongest support. We should
demonstrate to the former that no State has ever been
founded without a religious basis, and to the latter,
that the law of Christianity at bottom does more harm
by weakening than good by strengthening the constitution
of the State. To make myself understood, I have only
to make a little more exact the too vague ideas of religion
as relating to this subject.
Religion,
considered in relation to society, which is either general
or particular, may also be divided into two kinds: the
religion of man, and that of the citizen. The first,
which has neither temples, nor altars, nor rites, and
is confined to the purely internal cult of the supreme
God and the eternal obligations of morality, is the
religion of the Gospel pure and simple, the true theism,
what may be called natural divine right or law. The
other, which is codified in a single country, gives
it its gods, its own tutelary patrons; it has its dogmas,
its rites, and its external cult prescribed by law;
outside the single nation that follows it, all the world
is in its sight infidel, foreign and barbarous; the
duties and rights of man extend for it only as far as
its own altars. Of this kind were all the religions
of early peoples, which we may define as civil or positive
divine right or law.
There
is a third sort of religion of a more singular kind,
which gives men two codes of legislation, two rulers,
and two countries, renders them subject to contradictory
duties, and makes it impossible for them to be faithful
both to religion and to citizenship. Such are the religions
of the Lamas and of the Japanese, and such is Roman
Christianity, which may be called the religion of the
priest. It leads to a sort of mixed and anti-social
code which has no name.
In
their political aspect, all these three kinds of religion
have their defects. The third is so clearly bad, that
it is waste of time to stop to prove it such. All that
destroys social unity is worthless; all institutions
that set man in contradiction to himself are worthless.
The
second is good in that it unites the divine cult with
love of the laws, and, making country the object of
the citizens' adoration, teaches them that service done
to the State is service done to its tutelary god. It
is a form of theocracy, in which there can be no pontiff
save the prince, and no priests save the magistrates.
To die for one's country then becomes martyrdom; violation
of its laws, impiety; and to subject one who is guilty
to public execration is to condemn him to the anger
of the gods: Sacer estod.
On
the other hand, it is bad in that, being founded on
lies and error, it deceives men, makes them credulous
and superstitious, and drowns the true cult of the Divinity
in empty ceremonial. It is bad, again, when it becomes
tyrannous and exclusive, and makes a people bloodthirsty
and intolerant, so that it breathes fire and slaughter,
and regards as a sacred act the killing of every one
who does not believe in its gods. The result is to place
such a people in a natural state of war with all others,
so that its security is deeply endangered.
There
remains therefore the religion of man or Christianity
not the Christianity of to-day, but that of the
Gospel, which is entirely different. By means of this
holy, sublime, and real religion all men, being children
of one God, recognise one another as brothers, and the
society that unites them is not dissolved even at death.
But
this religion, having no particular relation to the
body politic, leaves the laws in possession of the force
they have in themselves without making any addition
to it; and thus one of the great bonds that unite society
considered in severally fails to operate. Nay, more,
so far from binding the hearts of the citizens to the
State, it has the effect of taking them away from all
earthly things. I know of nothing more contrary to the
social spirit.
We
are told that a people of true Christians would form
the most perfect society imaginable. I see in this supposition
only one great difficulty: that a society of true Christians
would not be a society of men.
I
say further that such a society, with all its perfection,
would be neither the strongest nor the most lasting:
the very fact that it was perfect would rob it of its
bond of union; the flaw that would destroy it would
lie in its very perfection.
Every
one would do his duty; the people would be law-abiding,
the rulers just and temperate; the magistrates upright
and incorruptible; the soldiers would scorn death; there
would be neither vanity nor luxury. So far, so good;
but let us hear more.
Christianity
as a religion is entirely spiritual, occupied solely
with heavenly things; the country of the Christian is
not of this world. He does his duty, indeed, but does
it with profound indifference to the good or ill success
of his cares. Provided he has nothing to reproach himself
with, it matters little to him whether things go well
or ill here on earth. If the State is prosperous, he
hardly dares to share in the public happiness, for fear
he may grow proud of his country's glory; if the State
is languishing, he blesses the hand of God that is hard
upon His people.
For
the State to be peaceable and for harmony to be maintained,
all the citizens without exception would have to be
good Christians; if by ill hap there should be a single
self-seeker or hypocrite, a Catiline or a Cromwell,
for instance, he would certainly get the better of his
pious compatriots. Christian charity does not readily
allow a man to think hardly of his neighbours. As soon
as, by some trick, he has discovered the art of imposing
on them and getting hold of a share in the public authority,
you have a man established in dignity; it is the will
of God that he be respected: very soon you have a power;
it is God's will that it be obeyed: and if the power
is abused by him who wields it, it is the scourge wherewith
God punishes His children. There would be scruples about
driving out the usurper: public tranquillity would have
to be disturbed, violence would have to be employed,
and blood spilt; all this accords ill with Christian
meekness; and after all, in this vale of sorrows, what
does it matter whether we are free men or serfs? The
essential thing is to get to heaven, and resignation
is only an additional means of doing so.
If
war breaks out with another State, the citizens march
readily out to battle; not one of them thinks of flight;
they do their duty, but they have no passion for victory;
they know better how to die than how to conquer. What
does it matter whether they win or lose? Does not Providence
know better than they what is meet for them? Only think
to what account a proud, impetuous and passionate enemy
could turn their stoicism! Set over against them those
generous peoples who were devoured by ardent love of
glory and of their country, imagine your Christian republic
face to face with Sparta or Rome: the pious Christians
will be beaten, crushed and destroyed, before they know
where they are, or will owe their safety only to the
contempt their enemy will conceive for them. It was
to my mind a fine oath that was taken by the soldiers
of Fabius, who swore, not to conquer or die, but to
come back victorious and kept their oath. Christians
would never have taken such an oath; they would have
looked on it as tempting God.
But
I am mistaken in speaking of a Christian republic; the
terms are mutually exclusive. Christianity preaches
only servitude and dependence. Its spirit is so favourable
to tyranny that it always profits by such a régime.
True Christians are made to be slaves, and they know
it and do not much mind: this short life counts for
too little in their eyes.
I
shall be told that Christian troops are excellent. I
deny it. Show me an instance. For my part, I know of
no Christian troops. I shall be told of the Crusades.
Without disputing the valour of the Crusaders, I answer
that, so far from being Christians, they were the priests'
soldiery, citizens of the Church. They fought for their
spiritual country, which the Church had, somehow or
other, made temporal. Well understood, this goes back
to paganism: as the Gospel sets up no national religion,
a holy war is impossible among Christians.
Under
the pagan emperors, the Christian soldiers were brave;
every Christian writer affirms it, and I believe it:
it was a case of honourable emulation of the pagan troops.
As soon as the emperors were Christian, this emulation
no longer existed, and, when the Cross had driven out
the eagle, Roman valour wholly disappeared.
But,
setting aside political considerations, let us come
back to what is right, and settle our principles on
this important point. The right which the social compact
gives the Sovereign over the subjects does not, we have
seen, exceed the limits of public expediency.46
The subjects then owe the Sovereign an account of their
opinions only to such an extent as they matter to the
community. Now, it matters very much to the community
that each citizen should have a religion. That will
make him love his duty; but the dogmas of that religion
concern the State and its members only so far as they
have reference to morality and to the duties which he
who professes them is bound to do to others. Each man
may have, over and above, what opinions he pleases,
without it being the Sovereign's business to take cognisance
of them; for, as the Sovereign has no authority in the
other world, whatever the lot of its subjects may be
in the life to come, that is not its business, provided
they are good citizens in this life.
There
is therefore a purely civil profession of faith of which
the Sovereign should fix the articles, not exactly as
religious dogmas, but as social sentiments without which
a man cannot be a good citizen or a faithful subject.47
While it can compel no one to believe them, it can banish
from the State whoever does not believe them
it can banish him, not for impiety, but as an anti-social
being, incapable of truly loving the laws and justice,
and of sacrificing, at need, his life to his duty. If
any one, after publicly recognising these dogmas, behaves
as if he does not believe them, let him be punished
by death: he has committed the worst of all crimes,
that of lying before the law.
The
dogmas of civil religion ought to be few, simple, and
exactly worded, without explanation or commentary. The
existence of a mighty, intelligent and beneficent Divinity,
possessed of foresight and providence, the life to come,
the happiness of the just, the punishment of the wicked,
the sanctity of the social contract and the laws: these
are its positive dogmas. Its negative dogmas I confine
to one, intolerance, which is a part of the cults we
have rejected.
Those
who distinguish civil from theological intolerance are,
to my mind, mistaken. The two forms are inseparable.
It is impossible to live at peace with those we regard
as damned; to love them would be to hate God who punishes
them: we positively must either reclaim or torment them.
Wherever theological intolerance is admitted, it must
inevitably have some civil effect;48
and as soon as it has such an effect, the Sovereign
is no longer Sovereign even in the temporal sphere:
thenceforce priests are the real masters, and kings
only their ministers.
Now
that there is and can be no longer an exclusive national
religion, tolerance should be given to all religions
that tolerate others, so long as their dogmas contain
nothing contrary to the duties of citizenship. But whoever
dares to say: Outside the Church is no salvation,
ought to be driven from the State, unless the State
is the Church, and the prince the pontiff. Such a dogma
is good only in a theocratic government; in any other,
it is fatal. The reason for which Henry IV is said to
have embraced the Roman religion ought to make every
honest man leave it, and still more any prince who knows
how to reason.
Now
that I have laid down the true principles of political
right, and tried to give the State a basis of its own
to rest on, I ought next to strengthen it by its external
relations, which would include the law of nations, commerce,
the right of war and conquest, public right, leagues,
negotiations, treaties, etc. But all this forms a new
subject that is far too vast for my narrow scope. I
ought throughout to have kept to a more limited sphere.