Before
commencing it is important to note that the answers below
are not about any given libertarian political party. Rather
they are about libertarianism generally and about people
who consider themselves to be libertarians, whether or not
they are members of a political party called The Libertarian
Party.
- How
is libertarianism distinguished from Objectivism?
- How
is libertarianism distinguished from conservatism or liberalism?
- How
is libertarianism distinguished from anarchism?
- Are
all libertarians individualist? Are all individualists
libertarian?
- Are
all libertarians collectivist? Are all collectivists libertarian?
- Are
all libertarians capitalist? Are all capitalists libertarian?
- Can
a religious person be a libertarian?
- Does
libertarianism value liberty? If so, why?
Q1. |
How is libertarianism
distinguished from Objectivism? |
A1. |
There
are certainly similarities between libertarianism and
Objectivism that have led many people, erroneously, to
conclude that libertarianism is Objectivism, or that
Objectivism is a form of libertarianism. For example:
- both
libertarians and Objectivists claim that they value
liberty.
- libertarians
and Objectivists use a "non-aggression axiom" to
determine when the use of coercive physical force
is appropriate.
- many who consider
themselves to be Objectivists join libertarian organizations.
However, there
are differences between libertarianism and Objectivism.
The differences result chiefly from the fact that,
whereas libertarianism is amoral and eschews the making
of moral judgments, Objectivism is a complete moral
philosophy requiring the moral person to judge
good from evil and to deny the fruits of the former
to the latter: Objectivism is actually libertarianism's antithesis in
this sense. Objectivism's adherence to an objective
moral philosophy gives rise to two key political differences
between Objectivism and libertarianism:
- according to
the Objectivist philosophy, every individual has
inalienable, natural rights of life, liberty and
property. Whereas some libertarians agree with the
Objectivists in this regard, the existence of natural
rights of life, liberty and property are not defining
characteristics of libertarianism. Many libertarians
disagree with the assertion that individuals have
natural rights of property, or oppose personal property
altogether.
- Objectivism
is, and all Objectivists are, purely capitalist.
There are no left-wing, socialist, or otherwise collectivist
versions of Objectivism. The same cannot be said
of libertarianism: it can only be said the some libertarians
are capitalist.
- Objectivism
has a single, unambiguous understanding of what it
means to be coercive: to
an Objectivist, inaction never constitutes the initiation
of coercive physical force.
Libertarians differ in their views about what constitutes
coercion (primarily, as a result of their differing
views about the propriety of rights of personal property).
For example, to some libertarians refusing to give
a starving man some of the food that you have grown
constitutes the initiation of coercive physical force,
on the belief that nobody should hold personal property,
and that a person should get what he needs from a
person with the ability to provide it. Other libertarians
agree with the Objectivist view that inaction never
constitutes the initiation of the coercive use of
physical force.
- anarchism is
compatible with libertarianism, but incompatible
with Objectivism. Some libertarians are anarchists:
they reject the need for a government and would prefer
not to have one: "Smash the State" is their motto.
In contrast, Objectivism holds government to be necessary
and
indispensable
on the
ground that
government places the use of coercive physical force
under objective control: government (including courts,
with their rules of evidence etc.) are seen as a
check on the dangerous passions of those who have
(or who think they have) had one or more of their
natural rights violated by a given suspect.
|
|
Q2.
|
How
is libertarianism distinguished from conservatism or
liberalism?
|
A2. |
Libertarianism
has certain clear and consistent characteristics and
beliefs. In contrast, neither conservatism nor liberalism
has a feature that can be said to be common to all who
consider themselves to be conservatives or liberals,
respectively.
In practice, conservatism
is not an ideology: rather, it is probably best described
as an opposition to major
change. Accordingly, the ideas
espoused by conservatism differ from place
to place,
from time
to
time: in a
Communist country, conservatives will typically support
Communist
ideas, in a mercantilist country they will support
mercantilism, etc..
Thus, for example, the federal Republican party in
the USA, or the Conservative
Party in Canada
are both called "Conservative" parties, but
their policies are in many ways radically different
and actually antithetical to one another. For example,
most Republican party members in the USA would oppose
a socialist health care system like that found in Canada,
but most
Conservative Party members in Canada would oppose eliminating
the government's socialist health care monopoly in
Canada. Despite the sometimes wide differences in policy
espoused by different conservative parties, most members
of each conservative party would nonetheless be called "Conservatives".
Like conservatism,
liberalism does not refer to an ideology,
though it may refer to several mutually exclusive
ideologies. It is a term
that may
fairly, and most reliably, be described
as a desire for
change. However, the term liberalism has also been used
to refer to particular ideological beliefs. It has
been used to refer both to a belief that
governments
should
not
intervene
in the economy, but also to refer to the belief that
the state
should intervene in the
economy
(for example,
interventionist economist John Maynard Keynes described
himself as a liberal). The term "liberalism" has also
been widely
used (particularly in the USA) to refer to social democrats
(socialists). As with conservatives, in
practice, liberalism tends simply to be a collection
of policies endorsed at a given
point in time by a political
party that has come to be identified by most people
as "Liberal".
That
said, there are certain fairly reliable observations
that can be
made concerning the differences between libertarians
on the one hand, and "conservatives" or "liberals" on
the other:
- libertarianism
is committed to the non-aggression axiom, whereas
many conservatives and liberals are not, and advocate
government actions that would actually violate the
non-aggression axiom: such things as the criminalization
of marijuana possession, of the raising of tax rates,
or of the burning of ones own flag, etc.
In fact, without trying in any way to be insulting,
many conservatives and liberals have no idea what
is meant by the term "non-aggression axiom".
- libertarianism
is intentionally amoral: it purposely avoids
the adoption of a code of good and evil (i.e., of
ethics). It would be fair to say that conservativism
and liberalism do not embrace a moral code, but
amorality is not a definining feature of conservativism
or liberalism: it
would
be false to
say
that conservatism
or
liberalism is intentionally amoral even if
some conservatives and
some liberals are amoral. Similarly,
it would be false to conclude that all conservatives
share a single code of ethics, or that all liberals
do so: there is no single, conservative or liberal
ethical code, per se. For example, liberals
in one jurisdiction or time may think it virtuous
to criminalize abortion, whereas liberals in another
jurisdiction or time may consider such criminalization
a vice.
- Whereas libertarians
argue that injustice can only result from a violation
of the non-aggression axiom, neither conservatism
nor liberalism limits the definition of injustice
in that way. Conservatives and liberals identify
injustice in a variety of ways and many conservatives
and liberals would consider certain acts to be unjust
even if the acts did not involve a violation of the
non-aggression axiom. For example, conservatives
or liberals may decide that possessing marijuana,
or cornering the coffee market are unjust activities.
- Many libertarians
are anarchists, whereas most conservatives and liberals
are not anarchists.
|
|
Q3.
|
How
is libertarianism distinguished from anarchism?
|
A3. |
Anarchism
is, essentially, the belief that there need not and ought
not to be a government. Libertarianism is compatible
with anarchism, but anarchism is not a defining feature
of libertarianism. A libertarian society need not be
anarchistic. Whereas some libertarians are anarchists,
many are not.
|
|
Q4.
|
Are
all libertarians individualist? Are all individualists
libertarian?
|
A4. |
Individualism
could most generally be defined as "any doctrine
or practice based on the assumption that the individual
and not society is the paramount consideration or end" (Webster's
New Collegiate Dictionary). Individualism is not a political
ideology per se, though some philosophies (e.g.,
Objectivism) are individualist in nature. Individualism
is not a defining feature of libertarianism. Many, but
not all libertarians are individualists. Some libertarians
are dedicated collectivists, eschewing such things as
property rights for individuals.
Nor is it the case
that all individualists are libertarian. Some individualists,
for example, are Objectivists.
|
|
Q5.
|
Are
all libertarians collectivist? Are all collectivists
libertarian?
|
A5. |
Collectivism
could most generally be defined as "any doctrine
or practice based on the assumption that society and
not the individual is the paramount consideration or
end". Collectivism is not a political ideology per
se, though some political ideologies (e.g., communism)
are collectivist in nature. Collectivism is not a defining
feature of libertarianism. Many, but not all libertarians
are collectivists. Some libertarians are dedicated individualists.
Nor is it the case
that all collectivists are libertarian. Some collectivists,
for example, are Stalinists.
|
|
Q6.
|
Are
all libertarians capitalist? Are all capitalists
libertarian?
|
A6. |
Capitalism
is a socio-economic system in which it is not illegal
for individuals to exclude others from the use of certain
things (e.g., land, chattel) and activities (e.g., reproduction
of written or recorded works). The power to exclude in
this manner is commonly referred to as "property
rights".
Only some (perhaps
most, in North America) libertarians are capitalist.
Other libertarians embrace collectivist systems for
the use of such things as land and chattel, etc., typically
distributing such things to each person according to
his/her need, and from each person according to his/her
ability.
Some capitalists
are libertarians, but not all. Some capitalists embrace
other political ideologies or philosophies (e.g., conservatism,
Objectivism). Other capitalists refrain from an explicit
adoption of a political ideology or philosophy altogether.
|
|
Q7.
|
Can
a religious person be a libertarian?
|
A7. |
Yes.
Libertarianism itself has no explicit code of ethics
(i.e., it is amoral), and that is arguably so that a
libertarian code of ethics cannot come into conflict
with any given libertarian's own ethical code (for example,
one derived from a religion). That said, if one's ethics
effectively dictated that the non-aggression axiom is
evil, or that ones laws must be drafted to combat evil
even in the absense of a violation of the non-aggression
axiom, one may find oneself unable to be true both to
libertarianism and
to ones
religion.
|
|
Q8.
|
Does
libertarianism value liberty? If so, why?
|
A8. |
One
highly regarded libertarian, anarcho-capitalist economist
Murray Rothbard, explained that libertarianism sees liberty
as a precondition for virtuous (i.e., good) conduct.
He argued that ones conduct cannot be judged good or
evil if one has not freely chosen to engage in the conduct
in question. For example, according to Rothbard's reasoning,
if a charitable donor chose to give money only because
he was told that he would be killed if he did not donate
the money, the donor's act of donating the money would
not have been virtuous: to be virtuous, according to
Rothbard, the donation would have to have been voluntary
rather
than coerced.
Of course, Rothbard's
explanation fails to explain why voluntary conduct
can be good whereas coerced conduct cannot: Rothbard
does not explain how he comes to the conclusion that
liberty
itself is virtuous. It
has been argued by some Objectivists (most notably,
Peter Schwartz of the Ayn
Rand Institute) that it is
actually a myth that libertarianism values liberty
or considers it good (see his "Libertarianism:
The Perversion of Liberty" in Ayn Rand's book, The
Voice of Reason). Schwartz argues that because
libertarianism is opposed to judging good from evil,
or morally valuable from morally worthless, libertarianism
cannot logically consider liberty to be good or valuable.
Schwartz argues that libertarianism's implicit or explicit
claim - that it holds liberty as its highest value
- is false and unwarranted; that libertarianism rejects
the making of moral evaluations such that it cannot
evaluate the desirability of liberty. Schwartz essentially
argues
that Rothbard's claim - that liberty is a precondition
for passing moral judgment on ones conduct - is illogical,
because such a claim involves an implicit moral
judgment: that liberty is good. Schwartz asserts that,
in fact, libertarianism is nihilistic, and that if
it ever became popular and politically powerful, the
libertarian movement would actually destroy liberty
(if unintentionally).
|
|
" libertarianism:
Important Distinctions, Questions and Answers" -
Copyright 2003, Paul McKeever. All Rights reserved.
Neither this page, nor any of
its contents, may be reproduced without express written
permission from Paul
McKeever.
Neither this page, nor any of its contents, may be
contained in a frame in another web site without written
permission, but everyone is free to link to this page.
Last
updated on
September 6, 2004
|